Visiting the home of Mateo Ricci in 1601, Li Zhizao, a young magistrate with an interest in cartography, spotted a map on the wall. The map showed not just the thirteen provinces and two capitals of Ming China, and not only Japan, Korea, Tibet and India, or coastal Africa to which Admiral Zheng He had sailed early in the dynasty, but six continental masses, plus extensive regions in white at bottom. Years later, after he fell ill and Ricci nursed him to health, Li became a Christian. Ricci’s greater calling was to map Christianity in relation to the Confucian classics on which Li, like all of the literati class, had been raised. Indeed, Li subsequently wrote a series of works describing ‘Heavenly Studies,’ based on the religious and scientific doctrines Ricci brought to China. But he never forgot that map, which literally expanded his view of the world.
Over the
four centuries since, a credible mapping of beliefs in relation to one
another, Ricci’s larger ambition, has become a pressing priority of emerging
world civilization.
Schemes
for relating world religions, like misfortunes, often come in
threes. Gibbon famously
said ancient Romans of different classes saw religions as equally true (commoners), false (philosophers) or useful (magistrates, Gibbon 1776: 43). In the late 1930s,
Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan borrowed the political terms ‘right, centre,
and left’ to describe models, taking Karl Barth and missionary-scholar
John Farquhar as Christian representatives of
the first two, and ascribing the third to Hindus
and liberal Christians (Radhakrishnan 1959: 347). Paul
Tillich described Barth’s position (with some sympathy) as ‘exclusivist,’
contrasting it with ‘pluralist’ and ‘inclusivist’ (Tillich 1963),
terms that have bedeviled analysis ever
since.
I am tempted to
illustrate the shortcomings of the latter two in reference to an ironic interlude
in the recent Boston tragedy, when two young terrorists hijacked a Mercedes SUV
with the legend ‘COEXIST’ on its rear fender, ‘C’ being the ‘Islamic’ crescent. We do share a planet, and the overt sentiment
of the bumper-sticker ought not be controversial. But the thinness of the ambition is matched
by the crudeness of its implicit theology.
How exactly does Islam, founded by a man who started numerous wars and
married numerous women (not all of whom were given a choice), rest alongside peace (‘O’
for the peace sign) and gender equality (‘E’)?
And isn’t the one-dimensionality of this row of icons, as misleading as
the strange bedfellows it creates?
Shouldn’t the crescent moon (originally a Turkish moon god) be in the
sky? And isn’t the cross (‘T’) set on a
hill, like the serpent in the wilderness, for a particular reason?
I will argue in this post
that when it comes to the question of truth -- I will not argue in relation to salvation here, which I see as "above my pay grade" -- the conventional theologies of religions are almost as fatally simple and
misleading. They are not only wrong as to guiding assumptions, they are unbiblical (especially pluralism and exclusivism), and are even logically incoherent. A model more orthodox and
traditional, radical and of greater explanatory power – a multidimensional sketch
of world religions rather like Mateo Ricci’s own – is needed. In a later essay, I will propose such a
solution, based on the idea of fulfillment.
Why Pluralism Fails
Philosopher John Hick |
In 1973, John Hick called
for a ‘Copernican
Revolution’ leading to equal respect for the world’s great religions. These he compared to
planets circling the sun (at first representing God, later a mysterious and
much-debated ‘Real’). For Wilfred Smith, rather than emphasize the discreet individuality of traditions
as Hick’s solar metaphor did, pluralism was a story that united humanity across
many divides: ‘What we seek is a
theology that will interpret the history of our race in a way that will give
intellectual expression to our faith, the faith of all of us, and to our modern
perception of the world (W Smith 1981: 125).’
Working with ethnic communities in
Birmingham, England, Hick began visiting mosques, temples, synagogues, and gurdwaras. He converted to pluralism from that
experience: ‘It was evident to me that essentially the same kind of thing is
taking place in them as in a Christian church – namely human beings opening
their minds to a higher divine Reality, known as personal and good and as
demanding righteousness and love between man and man.’ At first Hick called this Higher Reality ‘God.’ But that seemed to exclude Buddhist and
secular communities in which ‘salvation’ also seemed to occur. Hick therefore reasoned that each community
was in touch not with ultimate reality itself, which is after all beyond
personality and impersonality, good and evil, but with a ‘manifestation’ or ‘face’
of the ‘Real.’
Hick suggested that Yahweh is ‘the divine persona in relation to the Jewish people,’ and while
‘genuine, authentic and valid,’ belongs within that history. In the same way, Shiva or Krishna ‘are
divine personae in relation respectively to the Shaivite and the Vaishnavite
communities of India. Thus the many gods are not separate and distinct divine
beings, but rather different personae formed in the interaction of divine
presence and human projection’ (Hick 1980: 52-3).
Both Hick’s appeal to astronomy and
Smith’s to history echo Ricci’s desire to join East and West by mapping
traditions within one grand scheme. Both claim to posit credible ‘modern,’ that
is, scientific, models of universal knowledge.
But pluralism has floundered on epistemological,
historical, moral, and logical grounds.
Epistemologically, most travelled
people will concede that kindness, courage, self-control, honesty, and other
virtues can be found outside their native traditions, beginning, for
Christians, with the Good Samaritan. But why should we take that as evidence
that the religion of the person we admire is significantly true? One also finds kind atheists. Hick himself seems to concede the weakness of
this argument by including ‘humanism,’ ‘Marxism’ and ‘Maoism’ as valid
categories within pluralism. But if the
Real manifests itself by non-existence as easily as by existence, why credit it
with the latter virtue? If the 'Real' is just as easily 'revealed' as 'the Unreal,' Hick's model has reached its Reductio Ad Absurdum. Such an ephemeral concept becomes itself of no useful value.
Historically, how in fact has
‘salvific’ reform taken place? The Judeo-Christian model of salvation does not
predict that all believers will be uniformly superior to all unbelievers, but
that through the ‘seed of Abraham’ God will bless humanity. One might ask, ‘How
would the rise of science, the reformist thinking of Roy, Gandhi, or Sun, the
end of sati or foot binding, improvement
in the status of women, universal education, the long, fitful reform of
war-like European forest tribes that in American iconography culminates with
Martin Luther King quoting Isaiah before a statue of Abraham Lincoln, have been
different if Jesus remained in Nazareth and hewn wood?’ Considered
historically, as Hick advises us to do, ‘rough equality’ in salvific influence
of the great prophets can hardly be assumed. (Especially given a rich literature that intricately ties the greatest reforms to the Gospel.) One suspects some pluralists
stress the dark side of Christian history precisely to avoid serious analysis
of this difficult but not self-evidently inscrutable question.
Logically, how can salvation, which
for Hick reveals itself through virtuous deeds, be evidence of a Real that
cannot be called morally good? One might argue that followers of the Chinese
goddess Guan Yin act kindly by the grace of a benevolent and ontologically real
bodhisattva. But what would it mean to say the kindness of fatalists proves the
existence of an indifferent Fate? If anything, the evidence would seem to
undermine the claim, since the quality 'indifference' undermines the quality of 'kindness.' Yet tempted to call the Real at least analogously good,
Hick hurled the forbidden fruit aside:
‘I see the force of your argument.
Nevertheless I don’t think it can be accepted, because it violates the
principle that any comprehensive interpretation of religion must take account
of all the major traditions, and not just of one’s own.’ (Hick 1995: 61-2)
But why just major traditions?’ Why
exclude human sacrifice as salvific? Or torture of counter-revolutionaries?
This is not just a moral objection (that, shortly) but a logical conundrum.
Hick argued for the Real from the allegedly salvific character of ‘major’
traditions, even while denying that which alone could make that evidence mean
something – that the Real resembles what we want to be saved to, more than what
we cry to God for salvation from. Unable to affirm even that, the Real becomes
not only exclusive and unsupported, but self-defeating: its essential reason
for Being dissipates.
Moral Failings
Like all ineffable beings, Hick’s
Real must be that of which nothing can be predicated and therefore provides no
basis for preference. The Real cannot, Hick wrote, be described as ‘one or
many, person or thing, conscious or unconscious, purposive or non-purposive,
substance or process, good or evil, loving or hating’ (Hick 1992: 350). But
Hick seemed caught between the horns of exclusivism, and the consequences of
denying that, say, Mother Theresa acted in relation to the Real more
appropriately than Jim Jones. If the Real is not more loving than hating, why should we identify it with heaven which saves us, rather than hell, which seeks our damnation?
In an essay in Christianity and Other Religions (2001), Hick responded to such objections. I italicize key terms that, ironically, reveal the confusion
of his position with particular clarity:
‘We do not worship the Real in its
infinite transcendent nature, beyond the scope of our human categories, but the
Real as humanly thought and experienced within our own tradition. In religious
practice we relate ourselves to a particular “face” or appearance or manifestation of the ultimate divine
reality (2001: 169).
‘If we say that the figure of the
Heavenly Father is a manifestation of
the Real because it is salvific, and that it is salvific because it is a manifestation of the Real, are we not
moving in a circle? Reply: Yes, the hypothesis is ultimately circular, as
indeed every comprehensive hypothesis must be. The circle is entered, in this
case, by the faith that human religious experience is not purely imaginative
projection but is also a response to a transcendent reality. The hypothesis
should be judged by its comprehensiveness, its internal consistency and its
adequacy to the data – in this case, the data of the history of religions
(2001: 170).’
Hick used the word ‘manifestation’ three
times in these paragraphs. To ‘manifest’ means ‘to reveal, show, or display.’
What does it mean to say the Real ‘manifests’ itself through ‘faces’ of
ultimate reality, if what is manifest does not truly reflect that reality? Hick
smuggled in with his left hand what he extracts with his right: that God truly
reveals Himself by ‘saving,’ and by Hick’s quiet exclusion of some means of
salvation. The word ‘manifest’ carries one rhetorical advantage over synonyms:
it is vaguer and therefore does not reveal the contradiction so clearly as
‘display’ or ‘show’ might. This shows
clearly that on some level, Hick recoiled from the moral bankruptcy of his own
doctrine.
A nebulous ‘Real’ that has
no characteristics but that reveals itself (however unreliably!) in all
religions, may be comprehensive, but it is hard to see how it explains even
religious ethics. Why should a Real that
is not ‘good’ want to save? When Wilfred Smith described
religion as ‘a response to a divine initiative’ (Smith 1981: 30), how did that
help us understand Aztec sacrifices, sati,
or the Goan Inquisition? Pluralists
cannot, it seems, escape the fact that some ‘manifestations’ of the ‘Real’ save
more than others, or from insinuating that they thereby manifest the Real more
truly than others. Hick focuses on ‘great traditions,’ one suspects, because Aztec ritual,
Nazi metaphysics, or the ethical insights of Peoples’ Temple manifest the
ineffable Real rather too paradoxically.
The problem is not just that religion
is often horrible. It is that on
principle, discrimination (in either sense of the word) is not something pluralism can admit. Yet Hick’s basis for
accepting pluralism is that all major religions (he originally included Maoism,
which may have seemed like a good idea in 1973) are vehicles of salvation. If so, it is a salvation that would often bring glee to the forces of darkness.
‘Lead
me from the unreal to the Real’
Pluralists posit that all ‘great’
religions (at least) are more or less equally valid, true, or useful. John
Hick’s metaphor of planets circling the sun begs the question, ‘Valid, true, or
useful in relation to what?’ Just as a
solar system requires one center of gravity, so pluralism seems to require some
Ultimate that lends unity to different religions. Likewise, value judgments
about religious systems are meaningless except in reference to some standard.
Pluralism thus seems to demand something like ‘the Real,’ or the Enlightenment ideals
D’Costa says western pluralists generally smuggle into their systems. But any such entity seems doomed to be seen
as both too vague and too specific.
Wilfred Smith had a name for the error (common, he noted, in Christian tradition) of identifying transcendent or absolute truth with the manifestation through which one
Wilfred Canwell Smith, former director of Harvard's Center for the Study of World Religions. |
is introduced to it:
idolatry (Smith 1987: 58). But ‘transcendent’ or ‘absolute’ are attributes
ascribed to God, along with others, such as (the Stoics were whispering, even before
Paul announced this on Mars Hill) a belief that idols are inadequate to
represent Him. On what basis does Smith decree we should privilege two divine
attributes above all others? And how do these privileged and reified concepts –
or the Real – escape the charge of cultural conditioning? So pluralists must be equally guilty of this sin. In any case, by
berating Christian ‘idolatry,’ Smith in essence admits that even ‘pluralistic’
systems need to exclude. D’Costa explores this contradiction unrelentingly:
‘harmony (in Hick’s pluralism) is arrived at through the destruction and
neutralizing of the Other’ (D’Costa 2000: 27).
While Paul Knitter saw a ‘theocentric
universe’ as part and parcel of inclusive Christology (Knitter 1983), some find
even the attenuated ‘theocentricism’ of ‘The Real’ to be ‘implicitly exclusivist’
(Apczynski 1992). Looking at Hick’s system
from an even stronger position of Enlightenment rationality, John Apczynski saw
it as parochial and ‘retrograde,’ pock-marked with unacknowledged ‘narrowness’
and ‘exclusivism.’ D’Costa compared Hick’s ‘Enlightenment Exclusivism’
unfavorably to Hindu and Tibetan Buddhist versions (D’Costa 2000: 72-79): ‘It
privileges liberal modernity as the master code within which all the religions
are positioned, and neutered.’ Yet it was precisely to avoid exclusivism that
Hick fled orthodox Christology (McCready 1996), then theology, in the first
place.
Sikhism began as a "unity" religion; it later took up arms to protect its often admirable distinctiveness. |
The irony is, more of humanity is
arguably prepared to accept a concrete theism than a post-cultural and
ineffable ‘Real.’ Chinese Zen practitioners may deny God as Buddhists, yet
recognize the classical theistic term Shang
Di. Advaita Vedanta may dominate
philosophical Indian thought, but the masses (not excluding a Ram Mohan Roy or
Gandhi) pray to a God outside themselves they hope will hear and answer.
Cleanthes, Lao Zi, Epictetus, and Zhuang Zi (the second and fourth forming the ‘S’ in COEXIST)
arguably recognize a personal Supreme God even while espousing philosophies
often taken as pantheistic.
But the Jewish Scriptures portray
Yahweh as acting in relation to all peoples: judging, punishing, and rewarding, answering prayers, and preparing a universal Messiah. Early Christians read Plato
as ‘Moses in Attic Greek’ because they saw his theos (at least in Timaeus) as a Greek name for God. Paul also seemed to tacitly accept the Zeus of
Aratus as an acceptable synonym, while Augustine called Latins to a fuller
and saner conception of Jupiter. Even Australian
and Chinese tribes accepted names for the Supreme Being as given by neighboring
tribes. If God already transcends particular cultures, might not the Real
represent a constriction rather than an expansion of sympathies?
And while the ‘high religion’ of some
nations discourages monotheism, it is often present anyway. Anthropologist
David Lewis asked 651 Japanese if they believed in a ‘Being above man and
nature,’ and found almost two thirds believed (D. Lewis 1993: 242-3). I asked a
smaller sample of students at Nagasaki and Siebold Universities, giving them
pantheistic, atheistic, and polytheistic options, along with ‘There is only one
God, who made everything,’ and ‘There are many gods, but one God made
everything and is greater than the others.’ About one fifth chose one of these
two options, mostly the former, though only a few appeared to belong to
theistic religions (Marshall 2002: 88-9). In chapter 24 of the Lotus Sutra,
which influenced the popular Japanese Nichiren sect, the bodhisattva
Avalokitsvara functions much like Krishna in the Bhagavad Gita, a personal High God who reveals
himself in many disguises (Tagaki 2001: 257-9). Henotheism at least does not
seem inherently inimical to Japanese sensibilities.
It seems, then, that while a
Christian model of religions that begins with God must exclude models that deny
God, some degree of ontological exclusivism is probably an inescapable
consequence of the nature of logical disjunction, which ‘broader’ theologies
fail to escape, anyway. While theism ‘excludes’ non-theism, as ‘realism’
excludes non-realism, placing God at center of the Christian map of religions
is less provincial than commonly supposed, and seldom (if ever?) need ‘exclude’
any full human tradition.
So should we accept Hick’s Real
because it is real, or for social reasons? If the latter, is it moral or even
possible to believe something fundamental about the nature of reality simply to
build community? Anyway, given the tendency of ‘unity’ religions to evolve into
sects, why should this one succeed in unifying? And if unity is the goal, why
not start with the idea of God, or of a savior who dies for sin – beliefs that
include far more of humanity, and far more of humanity’s branches?
Nor, for all the problems the Real
creates, does it save Hick from accusations of ‘exclusivism’ on either side.
The search for something inert enough that everyone can believe in it collapses
on both flanks: it excludes the majority, whose concepts of the Absolute are
concrete, and it remains subject to charges of cultural bias when traces of
orthodox theology and Christology are (inevitably) found tainting the
ethnological headwaters of even the most prestine pluralism.
Why Exclusivism Fails
Leslie Newbigin |
I agree with Newbigin that the humbler alternative is to model
religions by what they aver as true, rather than claim to know who will enter heaven.
Yet one difficulty with pure ontological
exclusivism is finding anyone who holds it. The term seems to imply that truth
is limited to one tradition. But how likely is it that a developed system of
doctrines that millions of people have believed and often productively lived by
for centuries could be so wrong that its claims overlap with truth exactly
nowhere? John Hick found truth in Maoism: so did a pastor I knew who had spent
two decades in one of Mao’s prisons for his faith. Even the Tsarnaevs, if they were as informed
in Islamic orthodoxy as devoted to it, would be obliged to confess Jesus as the
‘Breath of God,’ as the Qur’an calls him.
Likewise, what can it mean to say the Christian faith is exclusively
true in relation to Islam, if one accepts the Muslim belief that there is one
good God who created all things?
Newbigin described
himself as exclusive in regard to the unique truth of Christianity (Newbigin
1989: 182) and the value of other religions for salvation, while being ‘inclusive
or pluralist’ about the work of God in the lives of non-Christians, and the
hope of their salvation. But in saying Christianity was uniquely true, Newbigin
did not mean truth is exclusively Christian.
In calling for a ‘new and unequivocal interpretation and elucidation’ of
‘exclusivism,’ Hendrik Kraemer likewise insisted that his own ‘exclusivism’
‘includes a real openness to truth wherever it may be found . . . ‘ (Kraemer
1960: 365) But if even Kraemer admitted
truth in other religions, then what exactly does exclusivism exclude?
Bristol University theologian of religions Gavin D'Costa |
In practice, Gavin D’Costa has
argued, people in all three camps admit some truth in
D’Costa himself sees Christianity as exclusive in the sense that the sum
of Christian propositions excludes the sum of competing packages. He therefore defines exclusivism as meaning
‘one single religion is true and all other revelations or religions are ultimately false,’ (D’Costa 2000: 20; my
emphasis). But if that is all we mean by exclusivism, then it seems an
implication of any belief, and not very descriptive or of much predictive
consequence. So it seems that either no
one is an ontological exclusivist, or everyone is. The circle that encompasses this camp is either
a point, or the whole (unmarked, undifferentiated) globe.
other traditions, but
hold their own views to be more fully true.
Perhaps we should understand pluralism
and exclusivism as not about truth and error, but about the set of facts one
chooses to focus on, or the attitude one adopts towards those facts.
Over decades of
research, Hick uncovered ‘immense spiritual riches’ in non-Christian
faiths (Hick 1987: 17), while Peter Cotterell found a ‘morass
of superstition, ignorance, exploitation, oppression, fear’ (Cotterell 1990: 51). One can find plenty of either. These extremes apparently describe how a
scholar focuses attention, rather than any useful generalization about the
varieties of religious experience or practice.
Challenges
for Inclusivism
But life consists neither in
including, nor excluding, but in discriminating between what ought to be taken
in, and what rejected. Cells grow by
taking in useful proteins, catalytic metals, water and oxygen, and by expelling
viruses, bacteria, harmful chemicals, and waste. Homeland Security operates, ideally, on
similar principles. Those who map world religions also face the need, as
Paul Tillich put it, to ‘subject’ elements in religion to some ‘central criteria,’
which like DNA will orchestrate the uses of those elements.
With the dubious success of modernism
at offering a universal narrative, and of post-modernism at escaping one,
compromise models are often proposed: ‘provisional pluralism,’ ‘anonymous
Christianity,’ ‘evolution of religions.’ Models that split the
difference between pluralism and
exclusivism are often jointly labelled ‘inclusivist,’ ‘acceptance,’ or (using the word rather vaguely, as Paul Knitter for example
does) ‘fulfillment.’ Hick explained the popularity of such models by claiming the
original, allegedly exclusivist Christian view of other faiths became ‘increasingly implausible and unrealistic,’ as Christians met
followers of other religions after the Voyages of Discovery. Afraid to ‘explicitly renounce’ the old orthodoxy, these views, like the epicycles
of late Ptolemaic astronomy, represent ad hoc, and doomed, attempts to escape the implications of contrary data (Hick 1980: 67). Hick thus defined the ‘older Christian
view of other faiths’ as ‘areas of spiritual darkness within which there is no
salvation, no knowledge of God, and no acceptable worship.’ Smith asked of those who
held such views, ‘May we not accept their ignorance as ignorance?’ (Smith 1981:
120)
Roberto de Nobili |
Should we not, rather, take such generalizations as
obtuse? Observers as astute as Tillich (Tillich:
1963: 26), Jaroslav Pelikan (Pelikan: 1985), Richard Fletcher (Fletcher 1999),
Lamin Sanneh (Sanneh: 1989), and Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan, more loosely (Radhakrishnan 1959: 331 and
343), have long recognized that ‘accommodation’ to positive elements in pagan thought has usually been part of mainstream
Christian theology. As Tillich put it, the norm has been ‘a dialectical union of acceptance and rejection, with all the
tensions, uncertainties, and changes which such dialectic implies’ (Tillich
1963: 35). Rather than don the cap of innovator, Jesuit missionary to India Roberto de Nobili cited extensive European precedent for accommodating
Brahmin culture (De Nobili 1971: 11, 21-87). Kwame Bediako and Wang Xiaochao
describe, in the context of young African and Chinese churches respectively,
how early Church fathers both criticized non-Christian thought, and affirmed important truths in it (Bediako
1992; Wang 1998). Justin Martyr, enthusing over how
Greek philosophy (‘the greatest possession’) draws one towards God, could hardly
have been meditating on the impact of fifteenth century Portuguese shipping.
Hick was right though to be leery of
ad hoc rationalization. He was right,
also, to demand that models be judged by ‘comprehensiveness, internal
consistency and ability to explain religious history (2001: 170).’ We have seen that his own pluralism fails badly
to achieve these goals, however. The Real is itself narrow, incoherent, and of little explanatory value.
Inclusivism is, however, a vague term that by itself does nothing to solve this problem. What does a given model of religions include? What does it still need to exclude? On what grounds? Inclusivists run
the risk of missing forest for trees, recognizing common traits without
setting them in a coherent theoretical framework. Terms like ‘redemptive analogies’ (Richardson 1980), ‘promises God gave the Chinese,’ or ‘the Gospel in Indian cups’ bandied about by modern missionaries, echo
the teleological
daring and evocative flare of ancient slogans like ‘tutors to Christ,’ ‘seeds of the
Word,’ ‘evangelical preparation.’ But analogies,
metaphors, fulfilled promises, and other correlations, need to be set into a workable intellectual
framework.
The challenge to ‘compromise’ theories is thus three-fold: (1) Are
they grounded in Christian theology, or (as Hick and others claim) mere ad hoc
adaptations? (2) Is the attitude to other religions they promote subtle and wisely
selective? Or are they susceptible to
Chesterton’s critique of the meson of
Aristotle: ‘Being a mixture of two things, it is a
dilution of two things?’ (Chesterton 1990: 93-4) (3) Do
they accurately predict new facts? In
other words, can an alternative to pluralism and exclusivism be found that is
not just vaguely fair-minded or a ‘moderate’ balance between orthodox rigor and
generosity of spirit, but follows cogent internal logic that discriminates and
predicts both noble and ignoble within ‘pagan’ traditions, and even lends it
new meaning?
A class of solutions that is richly biblical, claims theoretically coherence
and ambition, tells a story of all humanity, includes and excludes according to
clear-cut and orthodox criteria, derives at best from careful observation,
and provides a basis for practical acts of contextualization, is one that I call ‘Fulfillment
Theology (FT).’ My next essay will suggest that it
has been central to Christian thought, and argue that it sheds powerful light on
world religions.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Sincere comments welcome. Please give us something to call you -- "Anon" no longer works.